The Epistemic Significance of Current Clear and Distinct Perceptions in Descartes’ Epistemology
Abstract
In this article, I discuss the epistemic role that Descartes believed was played in knowledge construction by current clear and distinct perceptions (the ideas or propositions which appear most evident to us when we are attending to them). In recent literature, we can find two interpretations about the epistemic status and function of current clear and distinct perceptions in Descartes’ epistemology. The first may be called the psychological, the second normative. The latter states that current clear and distinct perceptions are utterly immune to all doubt, even before God’s existence is proven and the general rule of truth is established. Thus, their certainty is for Descartes not merely psychological, but normative. I endorse the normative interpretation for a number of what I believe to be cogent reasons. However, there are also some difficulties with it. Therefore, after presenting positive arguments for the interpretation (sections I–IV) I discuss the difficulties of textual and substantive nature that the normative interpretation needs to address if it is to be upheld (sections V–VI).
References
Bennett, Jonathan. 1990. “Truth and Stability in Descartes.” Supplementary volume, Meditations. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16:75–108.
Bennett, Jonathan. 2001. Learning from Six Philosophers. Vol. 1. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Broughton, Janet. 2002. Descartes’s Method of Doubt. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Broughton, Janet. 1999. “The Method of Doubt.” In The Rationalists: Critical Essays on Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz, edited by Derk Pereboom, 1–18. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Carriero, John P. 2009. Between Two Worlds: A Reading of Descartes’s Meditations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Carriero, John P. 2011. “The Cartesian Circle and the Foundations of Knowledge.” In A Companion to Descartes, edited by Janet Broughton and John P. Carriero, 302–18. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
Cottingham, John. 1986. Descartes. Oxford: Blackwell.
Cottingham, John.1986. Cartesian Reflections. Essays on Descartes’s Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
Curley, Edwin. 2006. “The Cogito and the Foundations of Knowledge.” In The Blackwell Guide to Descartes’ Meditations, edited by Stephen Gaukroger. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Della Rocca, Michael. 2011. “Taking the Fourth: Steps toward a New (Old) Reading of Descartes.” Midwest Studies In Philosophy 35 (1): 93–110.
Della Rocca, Michael. 2005. “Descartes, the Cartesian Circle, and Epistemology without God.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1): 1–33.
DeRose, Keith. 1992. “Descartes, Epistemic Principles, Epistemic Circularity, and Scientia.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 73:220–38.
Doney, Willis. 1955. “The Cartesian Circle.” Journal of the History of Ideas 16: 324–38.
Doney, Willis. 1970. “Descartes’s Conception of Perfect Knowledge.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 8:387–403.
Frankfurt, Harry. 1970. Demons, Dreamers, and Madmen. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill. Frankfurt, Harry. 1962. “Memory and the Cartesian Circle.” Philosophical Review 71:504–11. Gewirth, Alan. 1941. “The Cartesian Circle.” The Philosophical Review 50:368–95.
Gierulanka, Danuta. 1962. Zagadnienie swoistości poznania matematycznego. Warsaw: PWN. Gouhier, Henri. 1949. Essais sur Descartes. Paris: J. Vrin.
Gueroult, Martial. 1955–59. Malebranche. 3 vols. Paris: Aubier-Montaigne.
Hatfield, Gary. 2014. The Routledge Guidebook to Descartes’ Meditations. London: Routledge.
Hatfield, Gary. 2006. “The Cartesian Circle.” In The Blackwell Guide to Descartes’ Meditations, edited by Stephen Gaukgroger, 122–41. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Hume, David, and Tom L. Beauchamp. 2000. The Clarendon Edition of the Works of David Hume. Vol. 3, An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding: A Critical Edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kenny, Anthony. 1968. Descartes. New York: Random House.
Kopania, Jerzy. 1988. Funkcje poznawcze Descartesa teorii idei. Białystok: Dział Wydawnictw Filii UW.
Kulstad, Mark. 1977. “Frankfurt’s Interpretation of Descartes’ Validation of Reason.” The Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 8 (2): 7–16.
Larmore, Charles. 1984. “Descartes’ Psychologistic Theory of Assent.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 1:61–74.
Loeb, Louis E. 1990. “The Priority of Reason in Descartes.” Philosophical Review 99 (1): 3–43.
Loeb, Louis E. 1992. “The Cartesian Circle.” In The Cambridge Companion to Descartes, edited by John Cottingham, 200–35. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Markie, Peter. 1992. “The Cogito and Its Importance.” In The Cambridge Companion to Descartes, edited by John Cottingham. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Newman, Lex, and Alan Nelson.1999. “Circumventing Cartesian Circles.” Nolis 33:370–404.
Newman, Lex. 2004. “Rocking the Foundations of Cartesian Knowledge: Critical Notice of Janet Broughton, ‘Descartes’s Method of Doubt’.” The Philosophical Review 113:101–25.
Newman, Lex. Winter 2014. “Descartes’ Epistemology.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/descartes-epistemology/.
Nolan, Lawrence. 2016. The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Van Cleve, James. 1998. “Foundationalism, Epistemic Principles, and the Cartesian Circle.” In Descartes, edited by John Cottingham. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ragland, C. P. 2016. The Will to Reason: Theodicy and Freedom in Descartes. New York: Oxford University Press.
Williams, Bernard. 1978. Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.
Copyright (c) 2020 Roczniki Filozoficzne
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.